What is the difference between empiricism and nativism




















In one way it does, because it is in line with the basic Nativist theme that humans are tailored for their natural environment. But in another sense, the Empiricist might downplay the importance of this kind of Perceptual Nativism for the larger debate. Empiricists have always taken it for granted that we perceive as we do, in large part, because of our biological-psychological nature.

The traditional Empiricist focus has usually been on that part of our understanding that goes beyond what we actually perceive. So even if some of the priors involved in Bayesian models of perceptual processing are innate, the more critical arena for the Nativist is domain-specific cognitive processing, to which we now turn. Nativists would expect that the best Bayesian models of cognitive processing would have to incorporate innate priors that reflect domain-specific knowledge. Empiricists would expect that domain-specific priors are themselves learnable by Bayesian methods from experience plus domain-general constraints on learning.

We do not yet know enough to settle these questions, but they are now beginning to be addressed. Most recently, a number of theorists have used Bayesian techniques to model not just low-level perceptual processing but also aspects of higher-order cognitive processes. We already have sophisticated statistical analyses of the bottom-up part; the perceptual phenomena.

The challenge is to develop quantitative representations and analyses of the levels of top-down background knowledge that operate in particular domains. But the information contained in such a theory and the structural analyses of particular situations that this theory makes available, cannot yet be integrated into Bayesian statistical analyses. The challenge for Bayesians is to develop ways to recast the top-down elements and the analyses they make available in quantitative terms.

Only then will we be in a position to address whether and to what extent top-down information is learned or innate. We can use the case of language understanding, a well-studied area and arguably a Nativist stronghold, to illustrate how these Bayesian goals might be achieved.

The Bayesian says that the parser is able to do this because it can do a statistical analysis that integrates bottom-up and top-down information. We know how to assign the prior probability of a series of heads for a fair coin. But the question comes up again: how do we assign a prior probability to a linguistic representation, or to a complex visual scene, or to a complicated representation of the goals, roles, and perceptual beliefs of a player in one of the Theory of Mind scenarios?

The events are more complex, the representations of the events are therefore more complex, and the hypothesis space is more complex Chater et al. But even here, the problem of finding the best structure to assign to an input is daunting. As Chater et al. One problem is that the space of possible structures is often large and discontinuous; a second is that a direct application of probabilistic methods would involve assessing each structure by integrating a prior over its parameters, which seems computationally prohibitive; a third is that structures appear to be constrained in potentially highly abstract ways.

So it is only if Bayesians can get a handle on these representational and statistical problems, that they will be able to attack our question: how is the space of such structures generated in the first place?

Is there innate domain-specific information at work or is there a Bayesian hierarchy, a two-level-up Bayesian account that explains how this one-level-up information is acquired that is, a Bayesian learning-theoretic account that explains why the child represents linguistic input, for example, using tree structures, but integers in terms of a very different linear structure; for further discussion see Tenenbaum et al.

So, for example, children might know that animals are arranged in a taxonomy of a specific sort, and this prior background knowledge helps them learn about animals. But how do they get this prior? Do they learn it or is it simply there innately? To tackle these questions, all sorts of objects—structured representations one finds in a grammar, graph-structures one might find in a taxonomic representation of causal or kin relations, schemas applied to scene or event analysis, etc.

So there is much to be done. There is no a priori answer about how far up the Bayesian can go, and we do well to keep an open mind about the nature of the unlearned priors. It would be, at the very least, extremely surprising if nothing like this operates in human psychology.

Bayesianism, then, focuses the Nativist-Empiricist question on the priors. First, we need to find out where the background knowledge brought to bear in any particular task comes from. Is some part of it innate, or can its presence be accounted for in terms of higher-order Bayesian learning?

At some point, the Bayesian will come up against what is not learned by Bayesian methods at the very least, the Bayesian machinery itself [ 31 ] , and we will want to understand its specific character. Will it be information implemented in our perceptual systems or domain-general information that applies no matter what is being learned, supporting the Empiricist view, or will some of it be tailored to specific ranges and domains of knowledge, vindicating the Nativist?

We are still at the beginning of the road to the answers to these questions. It is important not to underestimate the challenge that Empiricists face. The Bayesian formalism might make it seem that all that needs to be explained is why the hypotheses compatible with the data are ordered in the way they are. So, for example, if it could be shown that the bias for a light from above explanation of the retinal image in section 3.

It is plausible that some of the priors relevant to scene recognition will be learnable in this way, so this may be right as far as it goes. But it does not get to the heart of the challenge. She must not only explain where the representation types come from, she must also account for the cognitive processing over these representation types. So even if there were a satisfactory Empiricist account of how the infant sorts inputs into the categories agent, hinderer, and so on, we still need a separate account of where the cognitive machinery that operates over these types comes from.

Without that, the infant will have a static typology with no way to anticipate the dynamics of the situation. Here, then, the Empiricist seems to have two choices. She must make the case that the machinery involved is either i generic and domain-independent, or ii domain-specific, but itself the product of higher-order learning.

The point is that the Empiricist must account for the repertoire of representation types that figure in the processing and for the machinery that does the processing.

The ultimate outcome of this debate will depend in part on how distinctive and complex the computational machinery turns out to be. If the engine for theory of mind dynamics only needs to do tree search or production rule application for example , then the case for Empiricism is strengthened, because these are very general computational capacities. Only the content of the specific rules or the content at the nodes will be domain-specific. But the more idiosyncratic the computational machinery in a specific subsystem—for example, a simulator that anticipated motions and locations in a dynamic physical scene—the greater the challenge for the Empiricist to explain how such an internal computational device is acquired from experience alone.

As we noted, although Bayesianism has had a special appeal for Empiricists, one can use Bayesian methodologies and remain open to Nativist possibilities. There is nothing to prevent a Bayesian from starting with an innate system of representations and computational machinery and then using Bayesian algorithms to figure out how learning from experience might work for such a system.

This approach is very much in line with the Core Nativist theorizing discussed in section 2. For a detailed defense of this methodology, see Lake et. In summary, then, Bayesianism appeals to Empiricists for at least two important reasons. First, because it reinstates learning from experience as a central process in cognitive development and change.

The lead role, again following Chomsky, was assigned to growth, understood simply as biological maturation. The second reason is that the current Bayesian mindset tends in some ways towards Empiricism. But Bayesianism also has some appeal to Nativists, because it focuses attention on the role of background knowledge in learning, and this is a theme that Nativists have pressed against bottom-up Associationist forms of Empiricism from the outset.

Nativists can welcome a renewed focus on learning, and join in the development of Bayesian theories of cognitive development. So in the end, Bayesianism—as an approach to cognitive development—is, like Connectionism, compatible with Nativism. For recent discussion of this last point, see Colombo ; for a more pessimistic assessment of the potential contribution of Bayesian approaches to psychology see Jones and Love Nativism, as we have seen, is a vigorous program in contemporary cognitive science.

But there is very little talk of Rationalism. The term is sometimes repurposed as another name for Nativism, and in some cases it is explicitly disowned, with Nativism taken to be the only plank in the original Rationalist platform worth saving.

But following up on our previous discussion, there is a case to be made that this common attitude misses an important and distinctly Rationalist feature of current Core Nativist research. Here we briefly sketch the key ideas behind this claim. The Classical Nativist-Empiricist debate is an expression of a disagreement about a bigger question: what is the cognitive mind and what is it for? For the Humean, all we have to work with is one experience and then another. For the Rationalist, mind is for understanding.

Understanding is of course connected to pattern detection and prediction, but it also involves making sense of the patterns at some deeper level. The Humean Empiricist rejects this search for depth as illusory; pattern detection is all understanding is or can be. Our point is that the Core Cognition approach retains this distinctively Rationalist emphasis on understanding.

Core systems like our intuitive physics and theory of mind help us construct models of the world based on innate abstract frameworks.

By deploying these theories we can go beyond the input patterns and come to understand not just how things look, but also what they are, why they are as they are, why they change in the ways they do, how things might be if relevant parameters were different, and so on. When the baby sees triangles pushing a square up a hill, she constructs a rich conceptualization of the scene that breaks things up into different kinds of elements, and assigns properties to the elements; properties involving agency, physical object, goals, private intentions, information states, rationality, number, shape, etc..

She can use this conceptualization—her intuitive theory—to understand the dynamics of what she sees and in that way make sense of the situation. Despite this commonality, Core Nativists are not one with Classical Rationalists.

Descartes took our innate Rational notion of the physical to be at the heart of the true physics. Newton showed that this was wrong, and that we needed to go beyond our intuitive physics if we wanted to get a deeper understanding of the world. Core Knowledge theorists reject the Classical assumption that our innate sense-making frameworks are necessarily true.

But true or not, what is innate provides a framework that we use to make sense of the world. To this extent, the Core Knowledge program revitalizes this key Rationalist idea. It remains an open question how we are to understand this notion of deep understanding. This search goes back at least as far as Plato.

But our point here has not been to defend the revival of this Rationalist theme; only to note the commonality. In conclusion, the studies that we surveyed in section 2 provide compelling evidence that we have been underestimating how much infants and young children understand about the world. The Bayesian framework we discussed in section 3 has the potential to address both issues at once.

It provides a systematic and quantifiable approach to development, and is at the same time open to incorporating innate elements. Whether it will succeed in unifying a learning-theoretic approach to cognitive development with the built-in representations favored by Nativists remains to be seen. The Chomskyan Revolution in Linguistics 1.

Empirical Findings and Theories 2. The Resurgence of Empiricism 3. Empirical Findings and Theories A full account—even a comprehensive survey—of Nativism in the cognitive sciences is beyond the scope of this entry. Hamlin reviews a series of findings that show that their preference for helpers is surprisingly nuanced. First, they are not simple helper-lovers. By the time they are 5-months-old, they prefer those who hinder hinderers to those who help them.

Second, their preferences are not just personal; they rise to the second order. They prefer other actors who help helpers and hinder hinderers to those who do the opposite. Fourth, and perhaps most surprising, by 8-months, babies do not judge actors on the basis of outcomes , but rather intentions. An unsuccessful helper is preferred over a hinderer and neutral bystanders at the same rate as a successful helper; the same holds for unsuccessful hinderers, mutatis mutandis.

The Resurgence of Empiricism The studies summarized in section 2 are representative of the Nativist resurgence. Figure 1. Bibliography Aguiar, A. Baillargeon, , 2. Cognitive Psychology , — Andrews, K. Zalta ed. Baillargeon, R. Bechtel, G. A companion to cognitive science , pp. Malden, Mass. Bloom, P. Oxford, OUP, — Burge, T.

Carey, S. Gelman, Carruthers, P. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Stich eds. New York: Oxford University Press. Chater, N. Chomsky, N. Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge: M. Reflections on Language.

New York: Pantheon. Colombo, M. Cowie, F. Csibra, G. Biro, O. Gergely, S. Darwin, C. Dehaene, S. Izard, E. Dennett, D. Descartes, R. Doherty, M. Hove, UK: Psychology Press. Downes, S. Feigenson, L. Ferrari, P. Visalberghi, A. Paukner, L. Fogassi, A. Ruggiero, et al. Flombaum, J. Fodor, J. Array Montgomery, Vt. Frisch, K. Array Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Gallistel, C. Gazzaniga, Ed. The Cognitive Neurosciences.

MIT Press. Garcia J, D. Gelman, R. Gergely, G. Gopnik, A. Schulz, eds. Griffiths, T. Supplement to special issue on Probabilistic Models of Cognition. Sobel, J. Gross, S. Hamlin, J. Laurence, eds. Hare, B. Call, B. Harman, G. Hauser, M. Tsao, P. Garcia, E. Moral minds: how nature designed our universal sense of right and wrong. Array New York: Ecco.

Helmholtz, H. Southall, Trans. New York: Dover. Hershberger, W. Hook, S. Hume, D. Selby-Bigge, rev. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Speech is for thinking during infancy. Onishi, and Amanda Pogue. Quinn, and Stephen E. Lea, New York: Oxford University Press. Waterfall, Arnon Lotem, Joseph Y. Halpern, Jennifer A.

Schwade, Luca Onnis, and Shimon Edelman. Category : Chapter 5. Belief-Bias vs Confirmation bias. Overconfidence: Definition, Examples, and Study. Hindsight Bias: Definition and Examples. Your email address will not be published. Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment. Skip to content.

Ordinary speakers regularly do say things which the nativists claim nobody ever says, and systematically fail to say things which the nativists claim people often say. In speaking the way they find natural, the population at large blows the nativist case to pieces.

I have been exposing the fallacies of linguistic nativism in print for forty-odd years now, but Chomsky, Pinker, and their followers have scarcely ever publicly alluded to my critique — Pinker never has, so far as I know. This is a point identified as remarkable by Paul Postal of New York University, in the foreword he contributed to my book. Suren Naicker quotes Pinker as writing in that he had never found time to read my book in the seven years since its first edition appeared, because he was too busy with new books of his own!

See footnote 12, pp. I wonder how one squares this statement by Pinker with the fact that, in a book he published in , he included his own take on a very specific argument original to my book, though without mentioning me or my book by name. I discuss this episode on p. The nativists are not fools.

They want the high-prestige invitations, the academic prizes, and so forth to carry on flowing in their direction. For that, they have to seem to the general public to tower above the fray, so that contrary views are not worth dignifying with an answer. But, to people who understand how science functions, this silence amounts to an admission of intellectual defeat.

He adds: claims that linguistic nativism is less a theory than a cult start looking plausible. He is an old man now; in he put his name to a paper co-authored with Marc Hauser and W. But even if Chomsky is no longer a Chomskyan, many other influential thinkers still are Chomskyans.

So it needs to be said for him. The idea that people begin knowing nothing but capable of learning anything may be boringly traditional; it remains the most adequate account of the facts.

More recently I have come to see it as a consequence of the way in which universities in the 21st century have been changed into businesses which prioritize the pursuit of revenue over the disinterested pursuit of truth via painstaking exact scholarship.



0コメント

  • 1000 / 1000